|
|
As far as I'm aware, assassination refers to the premeditated (I keep typnig 'premedicated' and having to correct myself. Hmmm...) killing of another for impersonal reasons, usually either political or monetary.
It's fairly basic, in my opinion. Either murder is, in and of itself, morally wrong, or it isn't. I believe it is always morally wrong, hence opposing capital punishment, violent regime change, illegal war, basic street level homicide, etc etc.
As mentioned above, we have to keep quite a tight hold on terminology here. Murder is pretty much defined as "an act of killing which is (legally/morally/ethically) wrong" - it's the description of a crime rather than an action. However, there are examples above in which an act of killing is not murder. Abortion, euthanasia - and, perhaps most resonantly, war. If you kill a helpless villager in war, you are a murderer. If you kill a member of an opposing force, you are a killer. This provision is covered by Jack in the idea of "legal war", but I think not covered sufficiently and, as politically-driven violence, war provides some useful points.
Of course, one can then say that somebody who takes up arms in an unjust (which includes but is possibly not limited to illegal) war is in fact a murderer. In which case, how do you define a just war? When does a soldier stop being a murderer and become either just a working stiff or indeed a hero?
Just war theory has a long and spotted history, going back at least to St. Augustine, and has recently been dug up by Elshtain. Where you identify jus in bellum is a matter of some debate, but the Elshtain model - which is interesting and useful in part because it is used to support a war in Iraq in which the Head of State was identified as a valid military targer, posits roughly:
1)A just war is motivated by the desire to protect innocents from harm.
2) A just war is openly declared by a legal authority
3) A just war is begun with the best intentions
4) A just war is a war of last resort, after every other option has been exhausted.
Clearly, one cannot (with much ease) obtain "legal authority" to assassinate, depending on how one defines "legal authority" - the UN would be unlikely to authorise the assassination of Fidel Castro, whereas the CIA did; see also Saddam Hussein. So, leave that aside. Can one apply the other criteria to a standard of "just assassination"? The assassination is motivated by the desire to protect innocents from harm, it is done with the best intentions, it is done as a last resort. Now, intentionality seems to me to be a bit bollocks here - if you are doing it to protect innocents, it is clear that your intentions are good, if you are not then no matter how good your intentions, you are not performing a "just assassination". However, we can now bring in two elements of previous just war theories. which I think are germaine:
1) A just war is one in which noncombatant immunity is sacrosanct.
2) A just war is one which is entered into with at least a reasonable chance of success, that is of achieving its aims.
These are about conduct as much as concept, but there are important, especially (2). Whatever you may think of the incumbent, his death, natural or otherwise, would actually not achieve the aims of stopping or reversing his policies. I would also say that all other options of expelling a leader elected by democracy (at least titular democracy) from power have not been exhausted - most obviously, there are the upcoming elections, but also impeachment (to provide one example). Arguably, a democratically-elected leader can never be assassinated justly by this model, because there is always another option - wait for the next set of elections. Arguably, one could then extend the model to all leaders, to say that there is always the option of waiting for natural causes to finish them off.
However. Let's take the theoretical(but not massively so) example of a dictator who plans to launch a campaign of extermination against a significant portion of his country's population, who are already subject to violent opporession. The generals of this country know that if he is not stopped, this campaign will begin in a month's time. During that month, they conclude that, due to the existence of a large and loyal secret police, it is not going to be possible to remove the dictator by peaceful means. They work out a means of killing the dictator that involves no other casualties. They then reach out to the leaders of the world and deliver assurances that they will stop the cruelties of this dictator, construct the apparatus of a democratic state, normalise relations with the rest of the world, and so on. The leaders of the world in turn give their undertaking that they will, once the deed is done, lend such support that the generals can be confident that their coup will not be overturned - that is, that the assassination will have a lasting effect and will protect the innocent of the nation.
Is that still utterly unacceptable at any time? That is, is it better to uphold the dictum against assassination, either on the grounds that it is better that the people rise up after a large enough number have been killed (that is, that killing is always morally wrong, and it is better that somebody else takes that "moral hit" many times than you do once), or that it there could not be enough certainty of improvement to justify the risk of unrest (a more pragmatic response). Mink's statement: it will never work, because by its nature it is anti-democratic and vile suggests a primarily moral objection (vile) but seems to limit speculation to cases where democratic actions are what is required, however one defines a democratic action. Assassination is not, clearly, the same as open elections...
(Incidentally, what I hope will be a final word on the "rough and tumble of debate". It's rhetoric, designed to imply that anyone disagreeing with the idea that assassination is never acceptable is doing so frivolously, seeing murder - Mink's term, not mine - as an extension of political discussion. One of the characterising elements of assassination, I would suggest, is that done well it precludes a right to reply. However, if we start complaining about Mink and Flyboy trying to knock lumps out of each other to the exclusion of all surrounding witnesses - Flyboy's sudden hurling into view of the redistribution of wealth immediately following being another example - we'll be here all year.) |
|
|