|
|
I'll start this off with a pre-amble, for those interested parties who don't study metaethics. I think this is necesary, because metaethics is a field that takes the most pressing philosophic problem - how should we live? - and makes it as finnicky and academic as any other branch of philosophy, meaning that questions of metaethics aren't much discussed except by experts (and their students, like myself).
Those of you who have sat down and wondered about what the nature of right and wrong is anyway might have come up with the idea that it's simply inappropriate to talk about a moral judgement being true or false. Everybody seems to agree, more or less, that wantonly setting children on fire is a pretty terrible thing to do, but judgements like 'abortion is wrong' is much, much more contested, to the point that it might seem that universal agreement on them is a pretty remote possibility. Subjectivism - the idea that a moral judgement is true or false depending on who you are - has some pretty enormous problems and I for one think it's simply an untenable position, because you are saying that the actual, honest-to-God, encoded-into-the-fabric-of-the-universe truth of a moral judgement changes willy-nilly from one person to the next. A position that is much more attractive to myself and most other people in the field is that moral judgements aren't truth-apt: they are less like factual claims and more like exclamations. The classical example of such an expressivist theory is Ayer's emotivism, also called the boo-hurrah theory, because to say 'it is wrong to burn children alive' is akin to saying 'boo, burning children alive!' and going 'helping your fellow man' is like 'hurrah, helping your fellow man!' When I say that everybody agrees that burning children alive is bad, what I am saying is that everybody disapproves of burning children alive, not that it is a truth of the world that burning children alive has the property of being evil. Moral codes then are expressions of some inner state, for Ayer's your emotional response to a given situation, and in Hume's terms 'children of the sentiments', hence the tern expressivism.
Note that this is not a normative, ethical claim. I'm not saying that every moral judgement actually says 'do what you feel is right'. People often judge the right thing to be soemthing they don't feel s right. This claim is metaethical - it is about the form and nature of moral judgements. It says that all moral judgements are seated on expressions of sentiment, even when the normative judgements make no reference to them: 'never lie' is not an expressivistic judgement, since it tells you to be honest even when you'd much rather not be, but expressivism claims that what drives you to never lie is a deep-seated attachment to honesty, not an intuition of the true moral code or something in that order. An excellent introduction and discussion of these types of questions is here: Article in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Now, the Frege-Geach problem is a knockout argument against emotivism: it runs as follows:
Moral judgements are supposed to be expressions of sentiment, and this seems plausible for statements like 'don't torment the cat'. But what about if such moral claims are embedded within valid (in the logical sense) arguments, like 'if it is wrong to torment the cat, then it is wrong to get little brother to torment the cat'. This argument only makes sense if the premise 'it is wrong to torment the cat' is truth-apt, either true or false, and remember than expressivism denies that this s the case. But that would render this perfectly ordinary use of a moral judgement nonsensical, thus, it can not be the correct account of that moral judgements actually are. You'll see that a theory as unsophisticated as Ayer's emotivism ('all moral judgements are merely expressions of emotional reactions') can not respond to this objection (raised by Peter Geach from a point he attributes to Gottlob Frege).
Because expressivism's opponents, like moral objectivism, have problems of its own, none of them less serious than the Frege-Geach problem, a lot of people (myself included) have stuck to expressivism, shoring it up against objections like these. The two strongest contemporary expressivist metaethics are Simon Blackburn's quasi-realism and Allan Gibbard's norm-expressivism. In quasi-realism it is noted that if enough people agree on certain judgements then these judgements can be handled as if they were cognitive and truth-apt, in the same way that it might not be a factual truth of the world that the Smiths is the greatest band in existence, but if you hang out at a Morrissey concert you could talk as if it was that way. In norm-expressivism, the current king of the expressivist roost, when we make day-to-day moral judgements we do so according to a certain moral code, one we understand and apply exactly as if it was handed down from the heavens, but the way we choose which system we use and what ultimately supports it is sentiment. Like, I might live my life by an exacting utilitarian code, but what brings me to do so is a deep-seated attachment to utilitarian values. In especially the case of norm-expressivism, the Frege-Geach problem is met because the argument 'if it is wrong to torment the cat, then it is wrong to get little brother to torment the cat' remains valid: if you use a norm where tormenting the cat is wrong, it is consistent with that norm not to get little brother to torment the cat.
*** Alert! Real question below! ***
Problem solved? Apparently not. An objection levelled at Blackburn's quasi-realism, which he in turn levels at norm-expressivism, is that an appeal to consistency is to give up the fight for expressivism, in Blackburn's words, consistency is 'on the other side of the Fregean divide'.
What on earth does he mean? I don't get it. It seems to me that he's saying that any system that has consistency in such a manner is already a cognitive (non-expressivistic) system, where judgements are at bottom truth-apt, not just approximately, and are about truths of the world, or what the speaker believes to be truths of the world (consider a rival metaethical theory, Mackie's error-theory, where all moral judgements are truth-apt, but all are systematically false, because there are no really existent moral properties which could make such judgements true). If the day-to-day ethical decision making is along the lines of a cognitive norm, in relation to which individual judgements are truth-apt, then I don't see how the Frege-Geach problem gets traction against norm-expressivism. I can see how appeals to consistency alone is not a sufficient response, because then it would be unclear whether a logical error is committed by someone who accepts that tormenting the cat is bad but sees no problem with getting little brother to do it, and whether such a person would merely be frivolous (this is how the argument was raised against Blackburn, btw, and is a big worry for quasi-realism). Earlier I had considered tackling this point at hand of Carroll's paradox which argues that any logical error simply is being frivolous itself, but now I see that that would not do the work I'd like (there's different standards for being frivolous in logic and being frivolous otherwise). So I'm left with no real grasp on what the Frege-Geach problem modified to norm-expressivism does, and correspondingly on how to tackle it. |
|
|