|
|
I still haven't read the book, though I really do intend to. I think it would help if I met someone who didn't think that Wolfram is a loony.
This is interesting. Can you explain why not knowing the why leads to a dead end - or (I suspect this is a related question, about the definition of a "dead end" maybe) what scientific progress would be, if not improved/total predictive power
Sure (with the warning that you should take everything I say with a pinch of salt). One point to make is that predictive power is a measure of success, but not the only goal that scientists have. Most scientists I've met want to understand how the world works and even if, ultimately, one can never answer the why and how questions, this doesn't mean that people want to give up on asking them. And science is as much about finding interesting questions as coming up with useful answers.
I think there is a more practical consideration. One of the striking features of cellular automata is that they produce very complex and difficult to predict behaviour. Great. So you start up a simplified model which on the small scale is only coarsely accurate, plug this into a cellular automaton and watch the pretty patterns producing the large scale emergent behaviour.
Cool. Now how do you know that you haven't just modelled your data samples? Maybe you have gone through a complex process which does little more than encode the information you already had. How can you tell? You can't, because the complexity that produced the result stands in the way of making the structural analysis that lets you answer questions like that.
(This is why I think Mr Spoong's example of Conway's Game of Life actually demonstrates the opposite of what they intend.)
But maybe you find that that you can model lots of situations. Which ones are going to work? When does the simulation break down? What are the significant features of the behaviour of your system (I'm thinking breaking points, resonant frequencies and so on)?
You can run the simulation lots of times in order to get some answers, and that can tell you a great deal, but a gap in understanding is not just a philosophical problem but places serious practical limitations on what you do. A chalk is a really good model of a piece of chalk, and you can learn a lot by smashing it, crushing it and stamping on it. But I don't think anyone would take seriously the notion that we should abandon material science and just test things (even though that is a large part of what material science is). Wolfram seems to be saying, with some added sophistication, something along those lines.
Now, of course, some of this could also be said of conventional science, but part of what Wolfram is doing is setting up a false dichotomy. No one objects to computer simulations (which is on some fundamental level what cellular automata are, albeit with a curious programming language), but why give up on the conventional stuff? You don't get relativity by designing a cellular automaton to model Newtonian collisions.
Has anyone noticed that there are fads in the application of mathematics to the sciences? - Decaying Insect
Yeah, its the sexiness of the paradigm shift, where people want to believe that the old fashioned, relentlessly incremental and rather difficult old stuff is for losers. Smart people use [insert current mathematical fad]. |
|
|